Add news
March 2010
April 2010
May 2010June 2010July 2010
August 2010
September 2010October 2010
November 2010
December 2010
January 2011
February 2011March 2011April 2011May 2011June 2011July 2011August 2011September 2011October 2011November 2011December 2011January 2012February 2012March 2012April 2012May 2012June 2012July 2012August 2012September 2012October 2012November 2012December 2012January 2013February 2013March 2013April 2013May 2013June 2013July 2013August 2013September 2013October 2013November 2013December 2013January 2014February 2014March 2014April 2014May 2014June 2014July 2014August 2014September 2014October 2014November 2014December 2014January 2015February 2015March 2015April 2015May 2015June 2015July 2015August 2015September 2015October 2015November 2015December 2015January 2016February 2016March 2016April 2016May 2016June 2016July 2016August 2016September 2016October 2016November 2016December 2016January 2017February 2017March 2017April 2017May 2017June 2017July 2017August 2017September 2017October 2017November 2017December 2017January 2018February 2018March 2018April 2018May 2018June 2018July 2018August 2018September 2018October 2018November 2018December 2018January 2019February 2019March 2019April 2019May 2019June 2019July 2019August 2019September 2019October 2019November 2019December 2019January 2020February 2020March 2020April 2020May 2020June 2020July 2020August 2020
123
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
News Every Day |

Justice Gorsuch’s Legal Philosophy Has aPrecedent Problem

pa href=https://www.cato.org/people/josh-blackman hreflang=undJosh Blackman/a/p div class=lead mb-3 spacer--nomargin--last-child text-default pJustice Neil Gorsuch is anbsp;proud textualist. According to this approach, what Congress intended, or expected, when it passed anbsp;law doesn’t matter. What matters are the words printed on paper. In practice, Justice Gorsuch will strictly follow the text of statutes, no matter what result it yields. Last month, he decided that the 1964 Civil Rights Act has always prohibited LGBTQ discrimination. Everyone had simply missed it for half anbsp;century. And at the close of the Court’s term, he determined that an 1833 treaty between the federal government and American Indian tribes was never formally rescinded. Who knew that eastern Oklahoma has been Indian Country all along?/p /div , div class=mb-3 spacer--nomargin--last-child text-default pIn both cases, Justice Gorsuch insisted he was sticking to the text, the whole text, and nothing but the text. Alas, he wasn’t. His interpretation was shaded by the work of justices who had not been so careful about text. And in both cases, Justice Gorsuch failed to acknowledge that the Court’s precedents were inconsistent with textualism. In doing so, he inadvertently undermined textualism’s justification. One can’t profess to follow the original meaning of anbsp;text while in fact following precedents that ignored that meaning. Going forward, he should criticize prior decisions that failed to take text seriously, and either reluctantly follow them, or formally abandon them./p pThe first of these two decisions wasnbsp;emBostock v. Clayton County/em. Here, the Court split 6–3. Justice Gorsuch wrote the majority opinion, which was joined by Chief Justice John Roberts, and the Court’s four progressives. Gorsuch parsed the text of Title VII of the Civil Rights Act of 1964. This statute made it unlawful for employers to “discriminate against” employees “because of … sex.” Justice Gorsuch did not begin his analysis by interpreting this text on anbsp;blank slate. Rather, he simply assumed that decades of case law had accurately interpreted the crucial phrasenbsp;emdiscriminate against because of sex/em. Indeed, he treated decades of precedent as part of the “law’s ordinary meaning” in 1964. This approach built an elaborate textualist framework on quicksand./p /div , aside class=aside--right aside--large aside pb-lg-0 pt-lg-2 div class=pullquote pullquote--default div class=pullquote__content h2 pIf Justice Gorsuch wants to move the law away from nebulous, flimsy reasoning toward more textualist, neutral principles, he must account for both text and precedent /p /div /div /aside , div class=mb-3 spacer--nomargin--last-child text-default pAll nine justices agree that the Court must determine the meaning of anbsp;statute, regardless of whether that meaning leads to anbsp;policy that is unwise or unjust. In this case, my view is that the phrase “discriminate against” must inform the meaning of “because of.” In thenbsp;a href=https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=3585940 target=_blank1960s/a, that phrase formed anbsp;single linguistic unit. Recently, anbsp;biopic was made about the life of Ruth Bader Ginsburg. Its title,nbsp;emOn the Basis of Sex/em, was an homage to the widespread understanding of what it meant to discriminate against anbsp;woman on the basis of sex. When these elements are combined, the phrasenbsp;emdiscriminate against because of sex/emnbsp;references discrimination based on bias or prejudice about anbsp;person’s sex, and not discrimination based on sexual orientation or gender identity. Justice Gorsuch relied on decades of precedents that focused primarily on “because of” and not the entire clause. Doing so eliminated the requirement that some sort of bias or prejudice exists based on anbsp;person’s sex. In effect, he severed the statute in half, and concluded that if sex plays any role in the discrimination, the employers’ actions are unlawful. The Georgetown University law professor Randy Barnett and Inbsp;a href=https://www.nationalreview.com/2020/06/justice-gorsuch-title-vii-cases-half-way-textualism-surprises-disappoints/ target=_blankhave described his approach/anbsp;as “halfway textualism.” Gorsuch followed old precedents narrowing anbsp;small component of the statute, even when those cases are at odds with the meaning of the entire statute./p pThe decision in the second case,nbsp;emMcGirt v. Oklahoma/em, was split 5–4, with Justice Gorsuch joined by the four progressive justices. This case considered whether Congress had formally “disestablished” an American Indian reservation that covers half of Oklahoma. No federal law dictates what precise steps are needed to disestablish anbsp;reservation. Thus, textualists have no relevant statute to parse. Instead, the courts have incrementally developed anbsp;century of case law about how Congress can eliminate American Indian sovereignty over territory. That framework, alas, is not itself textualist. The Court has never set out some magic words that Congress must utter to wind down tribal authority. Instead, the Court’s approach considers many factors that, when viewed in context, reveal an intent to disestablish the reservation./p pChief Justice Roberts, who dissented innbsp;emMcGirt/em, described the Court’s “well‐​settled” approach: “We determine whether Congress intended to disestablish anbsp;reservation by examining the relevant Acts of Congress and ‘all the [surrounding] circumstances,’ including the ‘contemporaneous and subsequent understanding of the status of the reservation.’” The Court has acknowledged that “explicit language” is not needed for anbsp;finding of disestablishment. Roberts explained, “The appropriate inquiry does not focus on the statutory text alone.” Without question, the Court has adopted anbsp;framework that favors Congress, to the detriment of the tribes. These precedents put anbsp;thumb on the scale of disestablishment./p pThis sort of fluid approach is, no doubt, anbsp;bitter pill for textualists to swallow. So innbsp;emMcGirt/em, Justice Gorsuch simply spit it out. Unlike innbsp;emBostock/em, Justice Gorsuch refused to treat the Court’s non‐​textualist precedents concerning Indian territory as part of the “law’s ordinary meaning.” He did not approach Congress’s entire body of work as the Court has instructed. Over the course of many years, Congress diminished the tribes’ authority, and established anbsp;commission to bring the territory under the jurisdiction of the state of Oklahoma. But Justice Gorsuch deemed this evidence too fragmented to establish anbsp;unified congressional intent. Rather, he inspected individual congressional actions that concerned the territory in anbsp;fragmented, balkanized fashion. Unsurprisingly, Congress did not meet his novel standard for disestablishment. As anbsp;result, Justice Gorsuch found that Congress’s 1833 promise to the tribes had not been explicitly repealed, and remained in effect. Congress hadn’t said the magic words. And how could it? Untilnbsp;emMcGirt/em, no one knew the precise textual standard that was needed to disestablish anbsp;reservation. In this case, Justice Gorsuch’s halfway textualism has literally cut Oklahoma in half./p pLet’s put these two decisions in perspective. Innbsp;emBostock/em, Justice Gorsuch quietly accepted precedent that paid little attention to text. Innbsp;emMcGirt/em, he quietly rejected precedent that paid little attention to text. In both cases, he erected elaborate textualist structures on top of anbsp;foundation well worn by the Court’s prior decisions. And in neither case did he acknowledge the relationship between precedent and textualism. In doing so, Inbsp;believe the justice erred./p pGenerally, the Supreme Court will follow the doctrine known as stare decisis, which is Latin for “to stand by things decided.” (I saynbsp;emgenerally/emnbsp;because justices of all stripes can always muster sufficient justification to overrule old decisions.) Textualists, particularly those of an originalist bent, have an especially tough time with stare decisis. In many instances, the text of anbsp;statute, or the Constitution, has anbsp;meaning that conflicts with the Court’s long‐​standing interpretation. Or the Court has adopted anbsp;method of reading anbsp;specific statute that requires consideration of subjective extrinsic factors, such as legislative history or policy concerns. What is anbsp;textualist to do? There are three general approaches./p pFirst, the textualist can acknowledge the conflict between text and precedent, but maintain that stare decisis compels anbsp;result that conflicts with textualism’s basic principles. This approach has the virtue of humility, even if it reaches the “wrong” result, at least by anbsp;textualist standard. Chief Justice Roberts spoke to this method in hisnbsp;emMcGirtnbsp;/emdissent: “Unless the Court is prepared to overrule these [old] precedents, it should follow them.”/p pSecond, the textualist can overrule the non‐​textualist precedent in order to enforce the statute’s natural sense. Here, stare decisis gives way to textualism. This approach has anbsp;significant downside, however: It disturbs arrangements that the people and government have come to rely on. Yet at least it has the virtue of candor: The jurist can explain thenbsp;emwhynbsp;/emandnbsp;emhow/emnbsp;of anbsp;departure from settled law. And Inbsp;find this sort of honesty refreshing. Justice Clarence Thomas is the member of the Court most likely to take Door No. 2. (Though innbsp;emMcGirt/em, he joined the chief justice behind Door No. 1.)/p pJustice Gorsuch, however, favored Door No. 3nbsp;innbsp;emBostocknbsp;/emandnbsp;emMcGirt/em. He professed to apply anbsp;form of unadulterated textualism. But he failed to account for contrary precedent. Innbsp;emBostock/em, he quietly baked into his analysis decisions from the 1980s and ’90s that were hardly textualist. And innbsp;emMcGirt/em, he demanded anbsp;level of textual precision from Congress that had never been demanded before./p pRepeating, over and over again, that Congress can amend the statute if it disagrees with the Court’s decision is not enough. Of course it can. But this argument goes only so far. Congress has been operating under certain presumptions for decades; it thought the scope of Title VII and the boundaries of Oklahoma had been settled long ago. But Justice Gorsuch maintains thatnbsp;emeveryonenbsp;/emwas wrong about Title VII for five decades, and thatnbsp;emeveryonenbsp;/emwas wrong about eastern Oklahoma for anbsp;century. At least in the unique context of Indian law, the Court had established a “well‐​settled” method of reading tribal law. And this framework is itself subject to stare decisis. (The Court has treated century‐​old antitrust laws in this common‐​law fashion.) Departures from that methods are permitted, but should be addressed./p pFinally, Inbsp;am not sanguine about the prospects for the future of textualism. Justices Ruth Bader Ginsburg, Stephen Breyer, Sonia Sotomayor, and Elena Kagan are savvy enough to recognize the limits ofnbsp;emBostocknbsp;/emandnbsp;emMcGirt/em. The quartet recognizes full well that Gorsuch’s opinions leave enough wiggle room to avoid anbsp;strict textualist holding in the future. They are in no sense tied to the mast of textualism. They are free to depart as needed./p pBut Inbsp;don’t think Justice Gorsuch is trying to lock them in. Indeed, Inbsp;have anbsp;newfound respect for him. In these cases, he was utterly disinterested in how his opinions would be received. He doesn’t care. There is no political calculation. There is no long game. There is no three‐​dimensional chess.nbsp;emBostocknbsp;/emdropped anbsp;a href=https://www.nytimes.com/2020/06/15/us/politics/gorsuch-supreme-court-gay-transgender-rights.html target=_blankthermonuclear bomb on the conservative legal movement/a, and Justice Gorsuch wasnbsp;a href=https://www.thepublicdiscourse.com/2020/06/65043/ target=_blankexcoriated by many of his supporters who felt betrayed/a. The first Trump appointee, no political slouch, must have anticipated that possible reaction. But he followed his principles. Inbsp;commend his temerity./p pMy disagreement, then, is methodological. Textualism, like originalism, must start from the blank slate of anbsp;statute, without regard to how the Court has interpreted that statute in the past. Justice Gorsuch cannot begin from the 50‐​yard line. He must start from his own end zone. In its present form, Justice Gorsuch’s textualism is far too fragmented to form anbsp;coherent jurisprudence. In the future, he must grapple with the interplay between stare decisis and textualism. When feasible, he should choose Door No. 2, and reject precedents that ignored textualism. If that approach is not viable, he should stay behind Door No. 1, and at least cast doubt on why that precedent is flawed, but follow it anyway. But Door No. 3nbsp;is misleading. It preaches textualism, but practices precedentialism. This approach, in the long run, will serve only to undermine textualism. If Justice Gorsuch wants to move the law away from nebulous, flimsy reasoning toward more textualist, neutral principles, he must account for both text and precedent./p /div Josh Blackman is anbsp;constitutional law professor at the South Texas College of Law Houston and an adjunct scholar at the Cato Institute.


Read also

I Am Begging You to Butter Your Hard-Boiled Eggs

Terrorist Boston Marathon Bomber Has Sentence Reduced Due to Jury Bias But Judge Amy Berman Jackson Ignored Same Jury Bias in Roger Stone Case

TikTok owner ByteDance accuses Facebook of ‘plagiarism and smears’



News, articles, comments, with a minute-by-minute update, now on Today24.pro




Today24.pro — latest news 24/7. You can add your news instantly now — here